BULLETIN
#32 Summer 2001
l BOOK REVIEW
- An Essay on Professional Ethics
l NINTH CIRCUIT DECIDES IOLTA CASE
CONTRARY TO FIFTH CIRCUIT DECISION
IN MAZZONE'S FAVOR
l MANDATING UNEMPLOYMENT
#32 Summer
2001 Page 1
BOOK REVIEW
An Essay
on Professional Ethics by Hon. George Sharswood, LL.D. 5th Ed.,
T. & J.W. Johnson & Co.
Reviewed by D. Tagliavia
With very little fanfare and with no hint of the significant merit
of Judge Sharswood's treatise, the authors of the preface to the
American Bar Association's Model Rules of Professional Conduct
state that the original canons of professional ethics approved
by the American Bar Association were based principally on the code
adopted by the Alabama Bar Association, which, in turn, was taken
from the lectures of Judge George Sharswood published in 1854 as
An Essay on Professional Ethics.1
In fact, the essay is remarkably rational. Given the mixture of
rationality and irrationality embodied in the Model Rules, it is
somewhat surprising to discover that one of its progenitors is
so strikingly sound. What is not surprising is that the essay was
written in the mid-nineteenth century.
Sharswood
began the study of law "under the preceptorship" of
Joseph Ingersoll, then one of the most distinguished advocates
of the Pennsylvania bar. Sharswood was admitted to the practice
of law at the usual age," and "being in easy circumstances
made no haste to secure business but continued his studies with
assiduous application."2 A period of practice and elected
office followed, culminating in Sharswood's appointment to the
bench of the District Court of Philadelphia. In the 22 years that
he sat on the district court, Sharswood wrote opinions in over
5,000 cases. In 1867 he was elected to the Supreme Court of Pennsylvania
and in 1879 became its chief justice.
Sharswood
first published his essay on professional ethics after delivering
it to law students
at the University of Pennsylvania
under the title of "A Compend of Lectures on the Aims and
Duties of the Profession of the Law." It begins with a discussion
of the objective nature of the derivation of the law: "[I]n
its true sense [the law] is not the work of mere will---not an
act of intellectual caprice. It is a severe and necessary deduction
from the relations of things."3
His understanding
of the nature and purpose of government is patently Lockean;
it
is firmly rooted in individual rights. "The final
cause," he says, "the reason why man was made a social
being---is that society was necessary to the perfection of his
physical, intellectual, and moral powers, in order to give the
fullest return to the labor of his hands, and to secure the greatest
advances in knowledge and wisdom. It is for no vain national power
or glory, for no experimental abstraction, that governments are
instituted among men. It is for man as an individual. It is to
promote his development; and in that consists his true happiness.4
The proposition would be still more accurate were it said---
Society is
constituted that men
#32 Summer
2001 Page 2
may be free---free
to develop themselves---free to seek their own happiness, following
their own instincts or conclusions.
Without
society---and government, which of course results from it---men
would not be free. An individual in a state of isolation might
defend himself from savage beasts, and more savage men, as
long as his strength lasted, but when sickness or age came on,
the
product of the labor of his hands, accumulated by a wise
foresight to meet
such a contingency, would become the prey of the stronger.
The comparatively weak-minded and ignorant would be constantly
subject
to the frauds of the more cunning."5 Equally remarkable as his embrace of these political principles
is the fact that Sharswood felt it necessary to begin a treatise
on legal ethics by endorsing them. Thus, he evidences at least
an implicit understanding that professional ethics in our legal
system must be derived from, and presumes, an understanding of
these principles.6
The lawyer
functions as part of what Sharswood calls the judiciary department
and
its function, in his view, is nothing less than
spreading "the broad and impregnable shield of its protection
over the life, limbs, liberty and property of the citizen, when
invaded even by the will of the majority." The "broad
and impregnable shield" is the system of laws that is the
basis for its adjudication. The lawyer, in acting for his client,
functions to assure the rightful application of those laws.
Having rooted
his code of professional ethics in the principles of rational
government,
Sharswood goes on to prescribe specific
precepts to guide counsel in his practice. Broadly stated, they
are "fidelity to the court, fidelity to the client, and fidelity
to the claims of truth and honor." From these broad principles
are derived some of the canons which are recognizable in today's
codes of ethics---the proscription against practicing deceit upon
the court, warm zeal in the maintenance and defense of a client's
rights, exertion of the utmost learning, avoidance and disclosure
of conflicts of interest, to name a few.
While some
of the precepts are familiar, they are cast in an interesting
historic light
and thus Sharswood's essay not only is commendable
for its insight, but it is intriguing. For example, if an attorney
represents a defendant he knows is guilty, Sharswood takes the
position that it is basely immoral for him to attempt to pin the
blame on someone else. By way of illustration, he describes with
considerable concern the circumstances "attending the defence
of Courvoisier, indicted for the murder of Lord William Russell," and
the accusation after Courvoisier's conviction that his barrister,
Charles Phillips, Esq., endeavored to fasten suspicion on others
although Courvoisier had confessed his guilt to counsel.7
Sharswood's
essay ends with the admonition "to use no falsehood." "Truth," he
states, "in all its simplicity---truth to the court, client,
and adversary---should be indeed the polar star of the lawyer." The
ill consequences of veering from the truth are felt not only in
the legal system but are, he recognizes, profoundly personal: "Let
him begin by swerving from truth or fairness, in small particulars,
he will find his character gone---whispered away, before he knows
it."
Copies of
Sharswood's essay are available in local academic law libraries.
They can also be purchased online. It is an essay well
worth reading, especially in light of ongoing efforts by the American
Bar Association to revise the Model Rules under the auspices of
the Ethics 2000
#32 Summer
2001 Page 3
Commission.
TAFOL will have more to say on the subject of ethics and about
Judge Sharswood in its forthcoming law review.
__________________________________
Notes: 1. The American
Bar Association approved 32 canons based on the Alabama model
on
August 27, 1908. Initially, the ABA treated the
canons as private law governing lawyers who chose to join the ABA.
However, in 1978, after the Antitrust Division of the Department
of Justice stated that it had antitrust issues with lawyers agreeing
together to abide by certain purportedly "ethical" restrictions
on, for example, advertising or fees, the ABA formally acknowledged
that its code was a "model" code, with the power of disciplinary
enforcement residing within the judiciary.
2. See the "memorial" preceding
the text of the essay's fifth edition.
3. Although
Sharswood admits of the necessity of man's discovering "the
relation of things," he is (like Locke) demonstrably religious
and contends that man made law can only aim at certainty.
4. Sharswood
is at some pains to say that he does not endorse a trend that
espouses
the idea that it is "the duty of government
to promote the happiness of the people." "The phrase," he
goes on to say, "may be interpreted so as to mean well, but
it is a very inaccurate and unhappy one. It is the inalienable
right of men to pursue their own happiness; each man under such
restraints of law as will leave every other man equally free to
do the same. The true, and only true object of government is to
secure this right."
5. Sharswood's
treatise contains an unusually emphatic endorsement of property
rights.
Sharswood states that although our Bill of
Rights are "not mere enunciations of abstract principles,
but solemn enactments by the people themselves, guarded by a sufficient
sanction," he goes on to say that they have not "carried
far enough their provision for the security of property from the
unjust action of government." Property, he says, "eminently
stands in need of every parchment barrier, which has been or can
be thrown around it." His statement is prescient, particularly
in light of the Ninth Circuit's recent holding in one of many IOLTA
cases. See the IOLTA article infra.
6. While Sharswood's treatise addresses professional ethics in
a legislative as well as an adjudicative context, he is quick to
admonish lawyers to take a comprehensive view of their responsibility
to the Constitution and laws both as legislators and practitioners.
7. Phillips denied the accusation.
Sharswood, however, is of the view that it is moral for an attorney
to represent a criminal defendant he believes is guilty. He believes
that to encourage an attorney to decline representation on the
ground of the defendant's guilt invests the attorney with arbitrary
discretion to determine a cause according to the attorney's own
notions of justice. "Every case," he states, "is
to be decided by the tribunal . . . upon the evidence, and upon
the principles of law applicable to the facts. . . . The lawyer,
who refuses his professional assistance because in his judgment
the case is unjust and indefensible, usurps the function of both
judge and jury." A number of Objectivists take a contrary
position: that the lawyer who makes his services available to
a defendant he believes is guilty, acts immorally. The legal
profession in general follows Sharswood's view.
NINTH CIRCUIT DECIDES IOLTA CASE
CONTRARY TO FIFTH CIRCUIT DECISION
IN MAZZONE'S FAVOR
With the Circuits Split, Supreme Court Review is Likely
The IOLTA saga continues. It is a study of how badly, and in how
many absurd directions, law can be made to go astray if it is
not objectively derived. In this case the culprit is the Takings
Clause of the Fifth Amendment of the United States Constitution.
Instead of generally proscribing the taking of property by the
government, it forbids taking without just compensation. A great
deal of doctrine has been spawned by the judiciary as a result
in an effort to define when government theft is appropriate and
when it is not, heaping bad principles on top of a doctrine that
is at root immoral.
In our last
issue we reported that former TAFOL president Michael Mazzone,
as plaintiff
in a case involving the Texas IOLTA program,
scored a victory in the Fifth Circuit when that court held the
program unconstitutional. Applying a so-called "per se" doctrinal
analysis of the
#32 Summer
2001 Page 4
Takings Clause,
the Fifth Circuit held that because the purpose of the Texas
IOLTA program is to take all the interest generated
from specified client-funds and use it to fund legal services
for the indigent, the program makes no provision for payment
of just
compensation. In fact, a just compensation remedy would entail
an "utterly pointless set of activities" because the
IOLTA program would be compelled to compensate the interest owners
dollar for dollar for the interest taken. Hence, the program was
unconstitutional. In contrast,
the Ninth Circuit utilized the so-called "ad
hoc" doctrinal analysis of the Takings Clause. It examined
an IOLTA program in Washington applicable to "Limited Practice
Officers" (LPOs) performing document preparation incident
to real estate closings. In applying the ad hoc analysis it used
a three-factor test to determine whether the program passed constitutional
muster. It examined whether there was an economic impact of IOLTA
regulations on the clients whose funds were deposited in IOLTA
accounts, the extent to which the regulations interfered with the
clients' distinct investment-backed expectations, and the "character" of
the governmental action.
As a preliminary
matter the Ninth Circuit concluded that there was no economic
impact
on the LPOs' clients from the taking of
their interest. Here is a synopsis of the legerdemain by which
the court reached that conclusion: Federal banking regulations
restrict the setting up of interest-bearing demand or checking
accounts (NOW accounts) for pooled funds of individuals who deposit
money in small amounts or for short periods of time. These regulations
apply to for-profit organizations. Thus, escrow and title companies
generally do not use NOW accounts because of the expense and difficulty
involved in crediting the proper amount of interest to each affected
person and because many of their clients are for-profit organizations.
IOLTA mandates the deposit of such funds in IOLTA accounts and
skirts the for-profit issue by dedicating the funds to indigent
representation. Therefore, the court "reasoned" that
because no interest would be earned on client funds in absence
of the IOLTA program, there was no economic impact on the clients.
Likewise, the Ninth Circuit concluded that the IOLTA program did
not interfere with the clients' distinct investment-backed expectations.
Lastly, and
most revealingly, the Ninth Circuit concluded that there was
no taking at all because
of the "character" of
the government action. Essentially, what the court said was that
if you view the principal and interest in the aggregate, what you
have is not the taking of 100% of the clients' property, but the "regulation" of
the aggregate. Such regulation is appropriate if the government's
action is imbued with the right "character."
It is so imbued
because both the banking industry and the legal profession are
already
highly regulated such that "this additional
unobtrusive regulation" does not exceed what is just and fair.
The program is just and fair in the court's view because the LPOs'
clients are not being singled out to bear a burden that should
be borne by the public as a whole. "They, as participants
in our legal system, are required to place their money in IOLTA
trust accounts that generate funds at no cost to them and that
expand [someone else's] access to the legal system from which they
benefit." This, of course, is a perversion of the word "benefit." Only
if one misconceives of a "benefit" in terms of collectivist
or altruistic notions can one imagine that a benefit has been conferred.
Clearly, the clients do not benefit individually since the interest
is unlikely to be used to defray their legal costs.
Just to be
sure the coffin was nailed down beyond all hope of either principal
or interest #32 Summer
2001 Page 5
escaping,
the Ninth Circuit stated that even if a taking had occurred,
no compensation would be due because the LPOs' clients
did not
lose anything. However, the Ninth Circuit remanded the case for consideration
of First Amendment issues. The court directed the district court
below to determine what speech, if any, was at issue and whether
the IOLTA program violated any rights the clients had emanating
from the First Amendment.
Given that there is now a split in the circuits on the issue of
whether IOLTA is unconstitutional under the Takings Clause, the
issue may yet go up again to the Supreme Court. Stay tuned.
MANDATING UNEMPLOYMENT
Living wage
laws, the altruist's modernized euphemism for compulsory wage
rates, have
met a setback, of sorts, in a Missouri lower-court
ruling. Attempting to avoid state-law preemption which barred cities
from imposing minimum wage laws higher than the state's, St. Louis
voters adopted a living wage ordinance requiring that contractors
who, directly or indirectly, deal with the city must pay $8.84
an hour, with health care benefits, or $10.76 without. Striking
down the ordinance, the Missouri Circuit Court found three fatal
errors: (a) the title of the legislation did not match its core
purpose, violating the state constitution; (b) imposing "comprehensive
family medical coverage" on city contractors was unconstitutionally
vague, and (c) the ordinance was in conflict with state-mandated
minimum wage laws. Elaborating the final point, the judge found
that private enterprise, having little or no direct connection
to the city's grants or subsidies, would be required to pay the
living wage rates. As an example, an accountant retained by a grantee
of the city to audit the grantee's books at a site that was receiving
financial aid would be subject to the wage requirements of the
ordinance, and the requirement would have to be maintained long
after the city's financial assistance was terminated. This, the
court held, caused the ordinance to be in conflict with the state
minimum wage law.1
The stricken
legislation was bad both morally and economically. Distilling
the paradoxes
of minimum wage laws, monopolistic labor
unions and unemployment, Ayn Rand in 1963 wrote, "As a result
of the high [union-coerced] wage rates, employers can afford to
hire fewer workers; as a result of curtailed production, employers
need fewer workers. Thus, one group of workers obtains unjustifiably
high wages at the expense of other workers who are unable to find
jobs at all. This---in conjunction with minimum wage laws---is
the cause of widespread unemployment. Unemployment is the inevitable
result of forcing wage rates above their free-market level. In
a free economy, in which neither employers nor workers are subject
to coercion, wage rates always tend toward the level at which all
those who seek employment will be able to obtain it.
"It is relevant to consider against what obstacles businessmen
have had to fight and to go on producing---when one hears labor
leaders proclaiming, in indignant tones, the workers' right to
a ''larger share'' of the ''national product.'' To paraphrase John
Galt: A larger share---provided by whom? . . . For excellent, more
detailed discussion of these issues, see Ludwig von Mises, Planning
for Freedom, especially the chapter entitled ''Wages, Unemployment
and Inflation,'' and Henry Hazlitt, Economics in One Lesson (New
York: Harper and Brothers, 1946), especially the chapters entitled "Minimum
Wage Laws'' and ''Do Unions Really Raise Wages?''2
The City of
St. Louis has been spared increased unemployment---temporarily.
Temporarily
#32 Summer
2001 Page 6
because the
court did not rule living wage laws inherently unconstitutional.
In fact, as a local leader of the Association
of Community Organizations
for Reform Now (ACORN) declared, the judge had laid out the
ways that the ordinance could be changed to make it legal.
_________________________________ References:
1.
Missouri Hotel and Motel Assn. v. City of St. Louis, Div. 3,
Mo.
22nd Cir. Ct. (7/18/01)
2. Capitalism:
The Unknown Ideal, Signet PB, pages 86, 88
__________________________________
Copyright © 2001
The Association for Objective Law. All rights reserved. The Association
for Objective Law is a Missouri non-profit
corporation whose purpose is to advance Objectivism, the philosophy
of Ayn Rand, as the basis of a proper legal system.
|